Three recipients of honorary degrees chat with the University of Denver Chancellor Chester M. Alter. Honorees are, from left: Sir Karl Popper of London, unnamed historian of Chicago Burlington and Quincy Railroad, and the Rev. Dr. Arthur Miller, pastor of Montview Presbyterian Church, Denver. Photo By Dave Mathias.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1970
Sir Karl Popper in conversation.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1979
Sir Karl Popper having a talk.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1979
Sir Karl Raimund Popper in 1979.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1983
London, United Kingdom
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper, 80, wearing the sash of the Grand Cross of the Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany, which he received for the influence his ideas have on German post-war political and philosophical thinking.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1987
Sir Karl Raimund Popper in 1987.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1990
Surrey, United Kingdom
Austrian philosopher Karl Popper, Surrey, 17th May 1990.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1990
Surrey, United Kingdom
Austrian philosopher Karl Popper, Surrey, 17th May 1990.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1991
Ostenstraße 26, 85072 Eichstätt, Germany
Karl Popper at the Catholic University of Eichstätt-Ingolstadt. Photo by Frank Mächler.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1991
Ostenstraße 26, 85072 Eichstätt, Germany
Karl Popper and Hanns W. Maull. Photo by Frank Mächler.
Gallery of Karl Popper
1992
Croydon, London, United Kingdom
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper poses at his home in Croydon, in London, England on August 31, 1992. Photo by David Levenson.
Achievements
Membership
Royal Society
Karl Popper was a member of the Royal Society.
British Academy
Karl Popper was a member of the British Academy.
American Academy of Arts and Sciences
Karl Popper was a member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences.
Lincean Academy
Karl Popper was a member of the Lincean Academy.
National Academy of Sciences
Karl Popper was a member of the National Academy of Sciences.
French Academy of Sciences
Karl Popper was a member of the French Academy of Sciences.
Phi Beta Kappa
Karl Popper was an Honorary member of the Harvard Chapter of Phi Beta Kappa.
Awards
Sonning Prize
1973
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper (left) being presented with the Sonning Prize by Thor A. Bak, Headmaster of Copenhagen University, Denmark, May 25th 1973.
Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany
1983
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper, 80, wearing the sash of the Grand Cross of the Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany, which he is seen receiving from the Federal Republic's Ambassador, Dr. Jurgen Euhfus, for the influence his ideas have on German post-war political and philosophical thinking.
Austrian Decoration for Science and Art
Order of Honour for Services to the Republic of Austria
Three recipients of honorary degrees chat with the University of Denver Chancellor Chester M. Alter. Honorees are, from left: Sir Karl Popper of London, unnamed historian of Chicago Burlington and Quincy Railroad, and the Rev. Dr. Arthur Miller, pastor of Montview Presbyterian Church, Denver. Photo By Dave Mathias.
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper, 80, wearing the sash of the Grand Cross of the Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany, which he received for the influence his ideas have on German post-war political and philosophical thinking.
Philosopher Sir Karl Popper, 80, wearing the sash of the Grand Cross of the Order of Merit of the Federal Republic of Germany, which he is seen receiving from the Federal Republic's Ambassador, Dr. Jurgen Euhfus, for the influence his ideas have on German post-war political and philosophical thinking.
The Two Fundamental Problems of the Theory of Knowledge
(The two fundamental problems of knowledge that lie at the...)
The two fundamental problems of knowledge that lie at the center of the book are the problem of induction, that although we are able to observe only a limited number of particular events, science nevertheless advances unrestricted universal statements; and the problem of demarcation, which asks for a separating line between empirical science and non-science. Popper seeks to solve these two basic problems with his celebrated theory of falsifiability, arguing that the inferences made in science are not inductive but deductive; science does not start with observations and proceed to generalize them but with problems, which it attacks with bold conjectures. The Two Fundamental Problems of the Theory of Knowledge is essential reading for anyone interested in Karl Popper, in the history and philosophy of science, and in the methods and theories of science itself.
(This book by one of the world's foremost philosophers of ...)
This book by one of the world's foremost philosophers of science presented a striking new picture of the logical character of scientific discovery - a picture which does full justice to the liberating effect of the Einsteinian revolution in physics and its immense impact upon scientific thought in general. For this new English edition Dr. Popper did his own translation and has written 150 pages of entirely new text. Ernest Nagel considered this work "a first rate contribution to the logic of scientific method. The book contains a very interesting chapter on quantum mechanics, which performs one of the few sensible analyses of the Indeterminacy Principle which I have seen in print. The book is highly stimulating and contains much that is bed-rock for future work."
(Karl Popper's The Poverty of Historicism is one of the mo...)
Karl Popper's The Poverty of Historicism is one of the most important books on the social sciences to have appeared since the Second World War. It is also the work of one of the most original minds of the twentieth century. At the time of its first publication in 1957, it was hailed by Arthur Koestler as 'probably the only book published this year which will outlive the century.' A devastating criticism of the idea that there are fixed laws in history and that human beings are able to predict them, Popper dedicated the book to all those 'who fell victim to the fascist and communist belief in Inexorable Laws of Historical Destiny.' Short and beautifully written, it has inspired generations of intellectuals, policymakers and general readers alike and remains one of the best books for gaining an insight into the ideas of this great thinker.
(A landmark defense of democracy that has been hailed as o...)
A landmark defense of democracy that has been hailed as one of the most important books of the twentieth century One of the most important books of the twentieth century, The Open Society and Its Enemies is an uncompromising defense of liberal democracy and a powerful attack on the intellectual origins of totalitarianism. An immediate sensation when it was first published, Karl Popper’s monumental achievement has attained legendary status on both the Left and Right. Tracing the roots of an authoritarian tradition represented by Plato, Marx, and Hegel, Popper argues that the spirit of free, critical inquiry that governs scientific investigation should also apply to politics. In a new foreword, George Soros, who was a student of Popper, describes the "revelation" of first reading the book and how it helped inspire his philanthropic Open Society Foundations.
Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge
(Conjectures and Refutations is one of Karl Popper's most ...)
Conjectures and Refutations is one of Karl Popper's most wide-ranging and popular works, notable not only for its acute insight into the way scientific knowledge grows, but also for applying those insights to politics and to history. It provides one of the clearest and most accessible statements of the fundamental idea that guided his work: not only our knowledge, but our aims and our standards, grow through an unending process of trial and error.
(The essays in this volume represent an approach to human ...)
The essays in this volume represent an approach to human knowledge that has had a profound influence on many recent thinkers. Popper breaks with a traditional commonsense theory of knowledge that can be traced back to Aristotle. A realist and fallibilist, he argues closely and in simple language that scientific knowledge, once stated in human language, is no longer part of ourselves but a separate entity that grows through critical selection.
(At the age of eight, Karl Popper was puzzling over the id...)
At the age of eight, Karl Popper was puzzling over the idea of infinity and by fifteen was beginning to take a keen interest in his father's well-stocked library of books. Unended Quest recounts these moments and many others in the life of one of the most influential thinkers of the twentieth century, providing an indispensable account of the ideas that influenced him most. As an introduction to Popper's philosophy, Unended Quest also shines. Popper lucidly explains the central ideas in his work, making this book ideal for anyone coming to Popper's life and work for the first time.
The Self and Its Brain: An Argument for Interactionism
(The relation between body and mind is one of the oldest r...)
The relation between body and mind is one of the oldest riddles that has puzzled mankind. That material and mental events may interact is accepted even by the law: our mental capacity to concentrate on the task can be seriously reduced by drugs. Physical and chemical processes may act upon the mind; and when we are writing a difficult letter, our mind acts upon our body and, through a chain of physical events, upon the mind of the recipient of the letter. This is what the authors of this book call the 'interaction of mental and physical events.' We know very little about this interaction; and according to recent philosophical fashions, this is explained by the alleged fact that we have brains but no thoughts. The authors of this book stress that they cannot solve the body-mind problem; but they hope that they have been able to shed new light on it. Eccles especially with his theory that the brain is a detector and amplifier; a theory that has given rise to important new developments, including new and exciting experiments; and Popper with his highly controversial theory of 'World 3.' They show that certain fashionable solutions which have been offered fail to understand the seriousness of the problems of the emergence of life, or consciousness, and of the creativity of our minds.
Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics: From the Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery
(Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics is one of the th...)
Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics is one of the three volumes of Karl Popper’s Postscript to the Logic of scientific Discovery. The Postscript is the culmination of Popper’s work in the philosophy of physics and a new famous attack on subjectivist approaches to philosophy of science. Quantum Theory and the Schism in Physics is the third volume of the Postscript. It may be read independently, but it also forms part of Popper’s interconnected argument in the Postscript. It presents Popper’s classic statement on quantum physics and offers important insights into his thinking on problems of method within science and physics as a whole.
Realism and the Aim of Science: From the Postscript to The Logic of Scientific Discovery
(Realism and the Aim of Science is one of the three volume...)
Realism and the Aim of Science is one of the three volumes of Karl Popper's Postscript to the Logic of scientific Discovery. The Postscript is the culmination of Popper's work in the philosophy of physics and a new famous attack on subjectivist approaches to philosophy of science.
In Search of a Better World: Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years
("I want to begin by declaring that I regard scientific kn...)
"I want to begin by declaring that I regard scientific knowledge as the most important kind of knowledge we have," writes Sir Karl Popper in the opening essay of this book, which collects his meditations on the real improvements science has wrought in society, in politics and in the arts in the course of the twentieth century. His subjects range from the beginnings of scientific speculation in classical Greece to the destructive effects of twentieth century totalitarianism, from major figures of the Enlightenment such as Kant and Voltaire to the role of science and self-criticism in the arts. The essays offer striking new insights into the mind of one of the greatest twentieth century philosophers.
The Lesson of this Century: With Two Talks on Freedom and the Democratic State
(In The Lesson of this Century Popper's purpose is to warn...)
In The Lesson of this Century Popper's purpose is to warn us against the increasing violence and egoism of our society. What solutions can we offer to the problems of the environment, demography and corruption? How can we prevent the violence our society engenders? How can we preserve our democratic system while at the same time paving the way for global peace? Popper believes that the philosopher has a duty to intervene in politics, and he utters a clear call to all of us to recognize our responsibilities. He reminds us that it is our actions which will create the world of tomorrow. The interviews in this volume were originally given to the Italian journalist Giancarlo Bosetti. The volume also includes the transcript of an interview about the moral dangers of television not previously available in English.
(All Life is Problem Solving is a stimulating and provocat...)
All Life is Problem Solving is a stimulating and provocative selection of Popper's writings on his main preoccupations during the last twenty-five years of his life. This collection illuminates Popper's process of working out key formulations in his theory of science, and indicates his view of the state of the world at the end of the Cold War and after the collapse of communism.
The Myth of the Framework: In Defence of Science and Rationality
(In a career spanning sixty years, Sir Karl Popper has mad...)
In a career spanning sixty years, Sir Karl Popper has made some of the most important contributions to the twentieth century discussion of science and rationality. The Myth of the Framework is a new collection of some of Popper's most important material on this subject. Sir Karl discusses such issues as the aims of science, the role that it plays in our civilization, the moral responsibility of the scientist, the structure of history, and the perennial choice between reason and revolution. In doing so, he attacks intellectual fashions (like positivism) that exaggerate what science and rationality have done, as well as intellectual fashions (like relativism) that denigrate what science and rationality can do. Scientific knowledge, according to Popper, is one of the most rational and creative of human achievements, but it is also inherently fallible and subject to revision. In place of intellectual fashions, Popper offers his own critical rationalism - a view that he regards both as a theory of knowledge and as an attitude towards human life, human morals and democracy. Published in cooperation with the Central European University.
The World of Parmenides: Essays on the Presocratic Enlightenment
(This unique collection of essays, published together for ...)
This unique collection of essays, published together for the first time, not only elucidates the complexity of ancient Greek thought, but also reveals Karl Popper's engagement with Presocratic philosophy and the enlightenment he experienced in his reading of Parmenides. As Karl Popper himself states himself in his introduction, he was inspired to write about Presocratic philosophy for two reasons - firstly to illustrate the thesis that all history is the history of problem situations and secondly, to show the greatness of the early Greek philosophers, who gave Europe its philosophy, its science and its humanism.
After The Open Society: Selected Social and Political Writings
(In this long-awaited volume, Jeremy Shearmur and Piers No...)
In this long-awaited volume, Jeremy Shearmur and Piers Norris Turner bring to light Popper's most important unpublished and uncollected writings from the time of The Open Society until his death in 1994. After The Open Society: Selected Social and Political Writings reveals the development of Popper's political and philosophical thought during and after the Second World War, from his early socialism through to the radical humanitarianism of The Open Society. The papers in this collection, many of which are available here for the first time, demonstrate the clarity and pertinence of Popper's thinking on such topics as religion, history, Plato, and Aristotle while revealing a lifetime of unwavering political commitment. After The Open Society illuminates the thought of one of the twentieth century's greatest philosophers and is essential reading for anyone interested in the recent course of philosophy, politics, history, and society.
Karl Raimund Popper was an Austrian-born British philosopher of natural and social science. He subscribed to anti-determinist metaphysics, believing that knowledge evolves from the experience of the mind.
Background
Karl Raimund Popper was born on 28 July 1902 in Vienna, which at that time could make some claim to be the cultural epicenter of the western world. His father Simon Siegmund Carl Popper was a lawyer from Bohemia and a doctor of law at the Vienna University while his mother Jenny Schiff was of Silesian and Hungarian descent. His parents, who were of Jewish origin, brought him up in an atmosphere which he was later to describe as ‘decidedly bookish.’ His father was a lawyer by profession, but he also took a keen interest in the classics and in philosophy and communicated to his son an interest in social and political issues which he was to never lose. His mother inculcated in him such a passion for music that for a time he seriously contemplated taking it up as a career, and indeed he initially chose the history of music as a second subject for his doctoral examination. Subsequently, his love for music became one of the inspirational forces in the development of his thought, and manifested itself in his highly original interpretation of the relationship between dogmatic and critical thinking, in his account of the distinction between objectivity and subjectivity, and, most importantly, in the growth of his hostility towards all forms of historicism, including historicist ideas about the nature of the ‘progressive’ in music.
Education
The young Karl Popper attended the Wiedner Gymnasium, where he was unhappy with the standards of the teaching, and, after an illness which kept him at home for a number of months, he left to attend the University of Vienna in 1918. However, he did not formally enroll at the university by taking the matriculation examination for another four years. 1919 was in many respects the most important formative year of his intellectual life. In that year he became heavily involved in left-wing politics, joined the Association of Socialist School Students, and became for a time a Marxist. However, he was quickly disillusioned with the doctrinaire character of the latter and soon abandoned it entirely. He also discovered the psychoanalytic theory of Freud and the individual psychology theory Adler (he served briefly as a voluntary social worker with deprived children in one of the latter’s clinics in the 1920s), and listened entranced to a lecture which Einstein gave in Vienna on relativity theory. The dominance of the critical spirit in Einstein, and what he considered its total absence in Marx, Freud, and Adler, struck Popper as being of fundamental importance: the pioneers of psychoanalysis, he came to think, couched their theories in terms which made them amenable only to confirmation, while Einstein’s theory, crucially, had testable implications which, if false, would have falsified the theory itself.
Popper trained as a cabinetmaker, obtained a primary school teaching diploma in 1925, and qualified to teach mathematics and physics in a secondary school in 1929. He undertook a doctoral program with the department of psychology at the University of Vienna under the supervision of Karl Bühler, who, with Otto Külpe, was one of the founder members of the Würzburg school of experimental psychology. Popper’s project was initially designed as a psychological investigation of human memory, on which he had conducted initial research. However, the subject matter of a planned introductory chapter on methodology assumed a position of increasing pre-eminence and this resonated with Bühler, who, as a distinguished Kantian scholar, a professor of philosophy as well as psychology, had famously addressed the issue of the contemporary ‘crisis in psychology.’ This ‘crisis,’ for Bühler, related to the question of the unity of psychology and had been generated by the proliferation of then competing paradigms within psychology which had undermined the hitherto dominant associationist one and problematized the question of method. Accordingly, under Bühler’s direction, Popper switched his topic to the methodological problem of cognitive psychology and received his doctorate in 1928 for his dissertation “Die Methodenfrage der Denkpsychologie."
In 1937 Karl Popper took up a position teaching philosophy at the University of Canterbury in New Zealand, where he was to remain for the duration of the Second World War, though he had a rather tense relationship with his head of department. Additionally, his wife had difficulty adapting to life away from her native Vienna and homesickness made her increasingly unhappy; this was exacerbated by the sheer relentlessness of Popper’s personal work ethic, which they both found exhausting.
The annexation of Austria in 1938 became the catalyst which prompted Popper to refocus his writings on social and political philosophy, and he published The Open Society and Its Enemies, his critique of totalitarianism, in 1945. In 1946, he moved to England to teach at the London School of Economics and became a professor of logic and scientific method at the University of London in 1949. From this point on his reputation and stature as a philosopher of science and social thinker grew enormously, and he continued to write prolifically - a number of his works, particularly The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), are now widely seen as pioneering classics in the field. However, he combined a combative personality with a zeal for self-aggrandizement that did little to endear him to professional colleagues at a personal level. He was ill-at-ease in the philosophical milieu of post-war Britain which was, as he saw it, fixated with trivial linguistic concerns dictated by Wittgenstein, whom he considered to be his nemesis. Popper was a somewhat paradoxical man, whose theoretic commitment to the primacy of rational criticism was counterpointed by hostility towards anything that amounted to less than total acceptance of his own thought, and in Britain - as had been the case in Vienna - he became increasingly an isolated figure, though his ideas continued to inspire admiration.
In later years Popper came under philosophical criticism for his prescriptive approach to science and his emphasis on the logic of falsification. This was superseded in the eyes of many by the socio-historical approach taken by Thomas Kuhn in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), who - in arguing for the incommensurability of rival scientific paradigms - reintroduced the idea that change in science is essentially dialectical and is dependent upon the establishment of consensus within communities of researchers.
Popper was knighted in 1965, and retired from the University of London in 1969, though he remained active as a writer, broadcaster, and lecturer until his death in 1994.
Karl Popper changed the way of scientific thinking. Scientific theories were thought to be tested by a process of verification. Popper showed they could only be tested by falsification. If a theory can be falsified, he said, it counts as science. Otherwise, it is pseudoscience or simply outside the limits of science. His hypothetico-deductive model of the scientific method has largely replaced the older deductive and inductive models. He was awarded prizes and honors throughout the world, including the Austrian Grand Decoration of Honour in Gold, the Lippincott Award of the American Political Science Association, and the Sonning Prize for merit in work which had furthered European civilization.
Popper tended to express Agnostic views, especially towards the end of his life. He also objected to organized religion in cases when he considered it using people's beliefs in unethical ways.
Politics
Popper’s best-known work outside pure scientific philosophy is his 1945 book The Open Society and Its Enemies. In it, he identified Plato, Hegel, and Marx as promoters of totalitarian government and therefore enemies of the open society. As might be expected, academics who approved of the philosophies of Plato, Hegel, and Marx leaped to their defense, accusing Popper of misinterpreting their ideas.
Popper said that although a democracy need not be an open society, liberal democracy was the best way to achieve one. Inspired by the achievements of the Ancient Greeks, he argued against tribal and collectivist societies, asserting that individuals should take responsibility for their own choices and actions.
Popper contended that Fascist or Communist totalitarian societies politicized science, preventing freedom of thought, leading to the degradation of knowledge. Totalitarian governments harmed people and societies by imposing policies on them that had been formulated using false theories.
Views
As Popper represents it, the central problem in the philosophy of science is that of demarcation, i.e., of distinguishing between science and what he terms ‘non-science’, under which heading he ranks, amongst others, logic, metaphysics, psychoanalysis, and Adler’s individual psychology. Popper is unusual amongst contemporary philosophers in that he accepts the validity of the Humean critique of induction, and indeed, goes beyond it in arguing that induction is never actually used in science. However, he does not concede that this entails the skepticism which is associated with Hume, and argues that the Baconian/Newtonian insistence on the primacy of ‘pure’ observation, as the initial step in the formation of theories, is completely misguided: all observation is selective and theory-laden - there are no pure or theory-free observations. In this way he destabilizes the traditional view that science can be distinguished from non-science on the basis of its inductive methodology; in contradistinction to this, Popper holds that there is no unique methodology specific to science. Science, like virtually every other human, and indeed organic, activity, Popper believes, consists largely of problem-solving.
Popper accordingly repudiates induction and rejects the view that it is the characteristic method of scientific investigation and inference, substituting falsifiability in its place. It is easy, he argues, to obtain evidence in favor of virtually any theory, and he consequently holds that such ‘corroboration,’ as he terms it, should count scientifically only if it is the positive result of a genuinely ‘risky’ prediction, which might conceivably have been false. For Popper, a theory is scientific only if it is refutable by a conceivable event. Every genuine test of a scientific theory, then, is logically an attempt to refute or to falsify it, and one genuine counter-instance falsifies the whole theory. In a critical sense, Popper’s theory of demarcation is based upon his perception of the logical asymmetry which holds between verification and falsification: it is logically impossible to conclusively verify a universal proposition by reference to experience (as Hume saw clearly), but a single counter-instance conclusively falsifies the corresponding universal law. In a word, an exception, far from ‘proving’ a rule, conclusively refutes it.
Every genuine scientific theory then, in Popper’s view, is prohibitive, in the sense that it forbids, by implication, particular events or occurrences. As such it can be tested and falsified, but never logically verified. Thus, Popper stresses that it should not be inferred from the fact that a theory has withstood the most rigorous testing, for however long a period of time, that it has been verified; rather we should recognize that such a theory has received a high measure of corroboration and may be provisionally retained as the best available theory until it is finally falsified (if indeed it is ever falsified), and/or is superseded by a better theory.
Popper has always drawn a clear distinction between the logic of falsifiability and its applied methodology. The logic of his theory is utterly simple: if a single ferrous metal is unaffected by a magnetic field it cannot be the case that all ferrous metals are affected by magnetic fields. Logically speaking, a scientific law is conclusively falsifiable although it is not conclusively verifiable. Methodologically, however, the situation is much more complex: no observation is free from the possibility of error - consequently, we may question whether our experimental result was what it appeared to be.
Thus, while advocating falsifiability as the criterion of demarcation for science, Popper explicitly allows for the fact that in practice a single conflicting or counter-instance is never sufficient methodologically to falsify a theory, and that scientific theories are often retained even though much of the available evidence conflicts with them, or is anomalous with respect to them. Scientific theories may, and do, arise genetically in many different ways, and the manner in which a particular scientist comes to formulate a particular theory may be of biographical interest, but it is of no consequence as far as the philosophy of science is concerned. Popper stresses in particular that there is no unique way, no single method such as induction, which functions as the route to scientific theory, a view which Einstein personally endorsed with his affirmation that ‘There is no logical path leading to [the highly universal laws of science]. They can only be reached by intuition, based upon something like an intellectual love of the objects of experience.’ Science, in Popper’s view, starts with problems rather than with observations - it is, indeed, precisely in the context of grappling with a problem that the scientist makes observations in the first instance: his observations are selectively designed to test the extent to which a given theory functions as a satisfactory solution to a given problem.
On this criterion of demarcation physics, chemistry, and (non-introspective) psychology, amongst others, are sciences, psychoanalysis is a pre-science (i.e., it undoubtedly contains useful and informative truths, but until such time as psychoanalytical theories can be formulated in such a manner as to be falsifiable, they will not attain the status of scientific theories), and astrology and phrenology are pseudo-sciences. Formally, then, Popper’s theory of demarcation may be articulated as follows: where a ‘basic statement’ is to be understood as a particular observation-report, then we may say that a theory is scientific if and only if it divides the class of basic statements into the following two non-empty sub-classes: (a) the class of all those basic statements with which it is inconsistent, or which it prohibits - this is the class of its potential falsifiers (i.e., those statements which, if true, falsify the whole theory), and (b) the class of those basic statements with which it is consistent, or which it permits (i.e., those statements which, if true, corroborate it, or bear it out).
Quotations:
"You can choose whatever name you like for the two types of government. I personally call the type of government which can be removed without violence "democracy," and the other "tyranny"."
"If we are uncritical we shall always find what we want: we shall look for, and find, confirmations, and we shall look away from, and not see, whatever might be dangerous to our pet theories."
"Whenever a theory appears to you as the only possible one, take this as a sign that you have neither understood the theory nor the problem which it was intended to solve."
"We are social creatures to the inmost centre of our being. The notion that one can begin anything at all from scratch, free from the past, or unindebted to others, could not conceivably be more wrong."
"There is an almost universal tendency, perhaps an inborn tendency, to suspect the good faith of a man who holds opinions that differ from our own opinions. It obviously endangers the freedom and the objectivity of our discussion if we attack a person instead of attacking an opinion or, more precisely, a theory."
"Science may be described as the art of systematic over-simplification - the art of discerning what we may with advantage omit."
"When I speak of reason or rationalism, all I mean is the conviction that we can learn through criticism of our mistakes and errors, especially through criticism by others, and eventually also through self-criticism."
"Our civilization has not yet fully recovered from the shock of its birth - the transition from the tribal or 'closed society', with its submission to magical forces, to the 'open society' which sets free the critical powers of man."
"Nazism and Fascism are thoroughly beaten, but I must admit that their defeat does not mean that barbarism and brutality have been defeated."
"I don't know whether God exists or not. Some forms of atheism are arrogant and ignorant and should be rejected, but agnosticism - to admit that we don't know and to search - is all right. When I look at what I call the gift of life, I feel a gratitude which is in tune with some religious ideas of God. However, the moment I even speak of it, I am embarrassed that I may do something wrong to God in talking about God."
"The whole thing goes back to myths which, though they may have a kernel of truth, are untrue. Why then should the Jewish myth be true and the Indian and Egyptian myths not be true?"
"Although I am not for religion, I do think that we should show respect for anybody who believes honestly."
Membership
Karl Popper was a member of the Royal Society, the British Academy, the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, the Lincean Academy, the Mont Pelerin Society, the International Academy of the History of Science, the National Academy of Sciences, the French Academy of Sciences, and an Honorary member of the Harvard Chapter of Phi Beta Kappa.
Royal Society
,
United Kingdom
British Academy
,
United Kingdom
American Academy of Arts and Sciences
,
United Kingdom
Lincean Academy
,
Italy
National Academy of Sciences
,
United States
French Academy of Sciences
,
France
Phi Beta Kappa
,
United States
Mont Pelerin Society
International Academy of the History of Science
Personality
Popper had a rather melancholic personality and took some time to settle on a career. He loved playing the piano, as his mother had done before him. He said that his skills as a pianist never matched hers. In contrast to his work in philosophy, where he challenged the old order, his musical tastes were very traditional – he liked Bach and Beethoven and did not appreciate new classical music such as Arnold Schoenberg’s atonal work.
Interests
playing the piano
Philosophers & Thinkers
Albert Einstein
Music & Bands
Johann Sebastian Bach, Ludwig van Beethoven
Connections
Popper married Josephine Anna Henninger (‘Hennie’) in 1930, and she oversaw his welfare with unflagging support and devotion, serving additionally as his amanuensis until her death in 1985. At an early stage of their marriage, they decided that they would never have children, a decision which Popper was able to look back on in later life with apparent equanimity.